Results 1 to 8 of 8

Thread: Secession and the Law -- Oppose Secession? You’re a statist.

  1. #1

    Secession and the Law -- Oppose Secession? You’re a statist.


    Secession and the Law


    Butler Shaffer

    I am amazed at the absence of reasoning found in the responses of many lawyers, law professors, political philosophers, and media opiners on the topic of political secession. As with political discussions generally, debate on this issue originates from either an individualistic or collectivist perspective. Those whose basic premises are aligned with institutional interests, and who regard such entities as ends in themselves, superior to the interests of individuals, tend to reject the rightful authority of men and women to alter or dismantle these institutions. If individuals are looked upon as being subservient to the interests of the state, those who share this opinion find it easy to treat secession as an illegal undertaking.


    The Achilles heel in this line of thinking is found in its contradiction with the modern theoretical foundations of political systems. For centuries, the state acquired its “legitimacy” from a mythical “social contract” by which the governed consent to live in accordance with rules created by their alleged “agents.” That no evidence exists for any state having been brought into being by a contract among those to be ruled, has not diminished the use of the fiction. Political systems have been created and sustained by violence; by the conquest – not the consent – of the governed.


    While I do not recognize a “social contract” as the origins of the state, I am quite willing to use the statists’ fabrication of such a transaction against them. By their nature, contracts are agreements voluntarily entered into by two or more persons to exchange claims to the ownership of property interests. Courts often refer to this voluntary nature as “mutual assent.” When one is forced, through threat of violence, to part with some property interest – as occurs when a street-mugger takes money from another at gun-point – a crime, not a contract, has taken place.


    For purposes of addressing the statists’ arguments re secession, I will assume what has never in fact occurred, namely, that a state system has come into existence by every adult male and female freely agreeing, in advance of its creation, to be bound by a contract to subject themselves to prescribed rules and procedures. But if such an arrangement can be generated by voluntary agreement – by contract – why may it not also be modified or terminated by a subsequent agreement? If we can voluntarily create such a system, why may we not also voluntarily end it?


    Implicit in the argument that it is illegal to dismantle a political structure allegedly created by some contract, is the unexplained assumption that the entity thus produced acquires rights that supersede the interests of the contracting parties. What is the reasoning that allows a tool to acquire a superiority of purpose and control over its creators? By what thinking does the Frankenstein monster become master over its producer?


    Furthermore, had such a contract been entered into, who would be bound by it? If a majority of the population had consented to this arrangement, how could a minority – who did not agreed to be so bound – be obligated under a contract principle? And under what reasoning could any subsequent persons – including the children of those who had contracted as well as any subsequent residents – be bound?


    Suppose that the Amalgamated Widget Company and I mutually agree to enter into a contract by which I will make my services available to the company in exchange for which they will pay me an agreed-upon salary. Suppose, further, that after ten years of working for Amalgamated, I decide to go to work for another firm. If Amalgamated wants me to stay, and cannot otherwise persuade me to do so, would it be “illegal” for me to work elsewhere? Would the company have a legal right to compel me to continue working for it? Such a conclusion is implicit in the statists’ rejection of the right to secede.


    When questions of secession are approached not in terms of consistency with some abstract, philosophic principle, but as a matter of realpolitik, it becomes evident who the real parties in interest are. It is not the system, the tool that advances the claim of its primacy, but those who have taken control of the instrument – or who were responsible for its creation in the first place – in order to use it to control others to advance their private purposes. The “cui bono” principle applies in this setting as much as it does elsewhere in human behavior: “who benefits,” not only from the creation of systems by which we organize ourselves, but in interpreting the words we employ in defining the scope of what such systems may do.


    When we attach ourselves so strongly to an abstraction that our minds have created, that we identify our very being with it; it becomes difficult for us to examine how such an attachment might contribute to the problems ensuing from our actions. To what extent, in other words, does our thinking contribute to the difficulties we experience in our institutionalized world?


    Whether we are considering questions in the realm of religion, science, law, or other subjects, we encounter a truth that few people are willing to consider: no system of thought can be self-validating. As Gregory Bateson emphasized, intellectual respect for any belief system cannot depend upon internal assertions, but must be analyzed from outside the system; to be tested by a metasystem (which, in turn, must be validated by yet another metasystem, ad infinitum).

    Neither religion, nor science, nor any philosophic beliefs, nor legal maxims, can self-justify itself. One finds an illustration of this idea in the old story of the man who is explaining to his son the structure of the universe, whose vastness, he tells him, rests on the back of a turtle. “But upon what does this turtle rest?,” the boy asks. “Upon another turtle,” the father responds. “But, again, what supports this turtle?,” the bewildered lad inquires. “Look,” said he father, “it’s turtles all the way down!”


    This endless regression is present in every system of thought, including the politico-legal system under question here. One of the first questions I ask my first-year students is this: “does the U.S. Constitution have any validity? And if so, why? Upon what basis does the government presume to rule your life?” This is one of those questions that few of us are ever encouraged to ask, leaving most of us to accept the political control of our lives with the same resignation we would the forces of gravity. Most of my students appear dumbfounded that such a question is even asked, particularly in a law school where the legitimacy of the Constitution is taken as a given. While the preamble presumes to speak for “We the People,” and Article V provides for the calling of a “Convention for proposing Amendments,” at no point is mention made of the right of people to secede, to withdraw from the system thus created.


    By what metasystem might the question of the justifiability of the Constitution – and, with it, the entire political structure of the United States – be analyzed? If it cannot be validated by its own self-serving language, to what standard might we turn? One possibility is the Declaration of Independence, a document that created no political institution, but provided the criteria by which any such bodies might be judged. Philosophic or religious texts might also be useful, but given connections presumed to exist between these two instruments, I will use the Declaration for purposes of comparison.


    The Declaration – heavily influenced by the thinking of such persons as John Locke – rationalizes the relations between individuals and political systems on a contract theory. Individuals being free, by nature, to protect their lives and property – but not to aggress or steal from others – may join together to form agencies to provide such protection – but with the same limitations vis-à-vis their neighbors. Should the political system, thus produced, exceed its permitted boundaries, it is the right of the people to “alter or abolish” it, and to create a new system to promote such legitimate ends. The Declaration clearly expresses the rights to “abolish” or to secede from a government that violates the individual rights that transcend the powers of the state.


    One can read through the Constitution for words that provide such precision in thought, but will not find it. In the 1857 words of Lord Macaulay, “Your Constitution is all sail and no anchor,” one finds the essence of state power in America. One provision in the Constitution that contains faint echoes of the sentiments of the Declaration is the Ninth Amendment, which reads: “The enumeration in the Constitution, of certain rights, shall not be construed to deny or disparage others retained by the people.” The logical implications of such words would lead thoughtful minds to acknowledge what the passage portends: the rights of human beings are of such infinite dimensions as to not be capable of verbalization. The Ninth Amendment was intended as a reminder of this fact.


    If the spirit of the Declaration was thus to be incorporated into the Constitution by this Amendment, one would expect hundreds or even thousands of cases to have arisen under it, and to have affirmed an expansive defense of the individual when confronted by the state. Such has not been the case. Only a handful of cases has arisen under the Ninth Amendment. This has contributed to the twisting of the thinking that places individual liberty above all interests of the state; thus creating a default-mode mindset that whatever “rights” people enjoy come from, and are “given” by, the Constitution. As a result of such intellectual corruption, it is commonplace for people to conclude that, if a purported “right” cannot be found in the specific language (aka as “strict construction”) of the Constitution, it does not exist!


    It is on the basis of such thinking that politicians, judges, and other statists assert that “secession” is “illegal.” If the Constitution does not specifically provide for this remedy, it does not exist; it is unlawful to pursue it. That such a proposition negates not only the Declaration of Independence, but the “social contract” theory upon which the state depends for bamboozling the public, is conveniently ignored by the statists. Many even go so far as to argue that the Civil War proved the illegality of secession, a conclusion that disregards the American colonials seceding from their then-present British government in a Revolutionary War aided by the ideas and spirit in the Declaration of Independence.


    “Secession” is not a legal question, any more than it is a “scientific,” or “technological,” or “medical,” or even a “mathematics” issue. It is, rather, a proposition that cannot be intelligently explored, or acted upon, within the confines of the system from which secessionists seek to withdraw. It is, in other words, a philosophical question; one that requires recourse to deeply-held principled beliefs. Just as those nineteenth century libertarians who sought to abolish slavery had to rest their arguments on metasystems of thought that transcended constitutional, statutory, and other formal legal standards; the secession question cannot be answered by the political authorities who control, for their benefit, the coercive machinery that continues to grind down, loot, and destroy those who seek to liberate themselves from its inhumane practices.


    From what extra-legal thinking can thoughtful minds find the inspiration and questioning with which to move outside the rigidly maintained boundaries of legalism? When we recall that the post-World War II Nuremberg defendants sought to excuse their murderous conduct with the plea that the acts they performed were not only allowed, but mandated by German law, we ought to be skeptical of allowing any system humans have created to be the judges of its own validity.


    Whether mankind is to survive, or bring about its own extinction, will depend largely on the premises that underlie our social organizations. Will they exist as voluntary, cooperative systems through which individuals can mutually achieve their respective interests; or will they continue to function as herd-oriented collectives that allow the few to benefit at the expense of the many? The answers to such questions are to be found only within our individual thinking. Secession does not begin at the ballot box, or in courtrooms, or in signing petitions, but in the same realm where you lost your independence: within your mind, and your willingness to identify with conflict-ridden abstractions.


    The Best of Butler Shaffer

    https://www.lewrockwell.com/2014/03/...ose-secession/



  2. Remove this section of ads by registering.
  3. #2
    I have read and understood this, and I subscribe to the ideas therein.

    If you've read and understood this, please chime in.

    We will never get certain people to read this, let alone understand it, and it would be nice if we could get a head count of who has actually put some thought into the matter.
    There are no crimes against people.
    There are only crimes against the state.
    And the state will never, ever choose to hold accountable its agents, because a thing can not commit a crime against itself.

  4. #3
    Anyone who subscribes to the founding principle that the only legitimate form of government is by consent of the governed must, if they are consistent, also subscribe to the radical right of secession regardless of what the Constitution says.
    The proper concern of society is the preservation of individual freedom; the proper concern of the individual is the harmony of society.

    "Who would be free, themselves must strike the blow." - Byron

    "Who overcomes by force, hath overcome but half his foe." - Milton

  5. #4
    OK, let us see what we have here.


    Secession and the Law


    Butler Shaffer

    I am amazed at the absence of reasoning found in the responses of many lawyers, law professors, political philosophers, and media opiners on the topic of political secession. As with political discussions generally, debate on this issue originates from either an individualistic or collectivist perspective. Those whose basic premises are aligned with institutional interests, and who regard such entities as ends in themselves, superior to the interests of individuals, tend to reject the rightful authority of men and women to alter or dismantle these institutions. If individuals are looked upon as being subservient to the interests of the state, those who share this opinion find it easy to treat secession as an illegal undertaking.
    So far, so good. There is nothing here, thus far, I would be able to dismantle. Mr. Shaffer is on the money.

    The Achilles heel in this line of thinking is found in its contradiction with the modern theoretical foundations of political systems. For centuries, the state acquired its “legitimacy” from a mythical “social contract” by which the governed consent to live in accordance with rules created by their alleged “agents.” That no evidence exists for any state having been brought into being by a contract among those to be ruled, has not diminished the use of the fiction. Political systems have been created and sustained by violence; by the conquest – not the consent – of the governed.
    Here I find some issue. The first line implicitly assumes that the "modern theoretical foundations of political systems" are somehow authoritative on the subject. This, of course, depends on the specific theory in question. Therefore, his statement is not sufficiently specific. In general, I would say that such theory really does not matter a whit in any case unless it is based upon, cognizant of, and is in perfect structural accord with the fundamental moral foundations of proper human relations. Works such as the Canon of Human Sovereignty are based on a proper derivation of such foundations. Any political theory addressing "political systems" in terms of what is right and wrong with such systems that is not in full accord with proper moral principles is invalid and merits zero consideration and absolute dismissal.

    Secondly, he refers to "the state" in a very dangerously ambiguous manner. His timbre and usage of the term strongly suggests reference to an entity in sé, which of course is not the case. Because there is no such thing as "the state" in itself, "it" cannot acquire anything because there is nothing to do the acquiring, save the players acting their roles in accord with the loosely contrived stage script we may call "the state". This may seem nit-picky in semantics, but I assure you that the difference here is not only fundamental, but absolutely central in its importance as it has a tremendously powerful effect on the cognition of those who subscribe to this fiction. If you believe your arm is off, it matters not a whit whether it actually is. People who believe they are dying often do by simple virtue of the belief and what it precipitates in physical terms.

    The remainder is on the money.

    While I do not recognize a “social contract” as the origins of the state, I am quite willing to use the statists’ fabrication of such a transaction against them. By their nature, contracts are agreementsvoluntarily entered into by two or more persons to exchange claims to the ownership of property interests. Courts often refer to this voluntary nature as “mutual assent.” When one is forced, through threat of violence, to part with some property interest – as occurs when a street-mugger takes money from another at gun-point – a crime, not a contract, has taken place.
    This is brilliantly on point. Clear, concise, and dead-nuts on the money.

    For purposes of addressing the statists’ arguments re secession, I will assume what has never in fact occurred, namely, that a state system has come into existence by every adult male and female freely agreeing, in advance of its creation, to be bound by a contract to subject themselves to prescribed rules and procedures. But if such an arrangement can be generated by voluntary agreement – by contract – why may it not also be modified or terminated by a subsequent agreement? If we can voluntarily create such a system, why may we not also voluntarily end it?
    Same as above. He has turned the tables adroitly on the statist position.

    Implicit in the argument that it is illegal to dismantle a political structure allegedly created by some contract, is the unexplained assumption that the entity thus produced acquires rights that supersede the interests of the contracting parties. What is the reasoning that allows a tool to acquire a superiority of purpose and control over its creators? By what thinking does the Frankenstein monster become master over its producer?
    More pointed brilliance. These are precisely the questions the statists are never able to answer with even the least measure of satisfactory effect.

    Furthermore, had such a contract been entered into, who would be bound by it? If a majority of the population had consented to this arrangement, how could a minority – who did not agreed to be so bound – be obligated under a contract principle? And under what reasoning could any subsequent persons – including the children of those who had contracted as well as any subsequent residents – be bound?
    Hammering home the point over and over. Well done.

    Suppose that the Amalgamated Widget Company and I mutually agree to enter into a contract by which I will make my services available to the company in exchange for which they will pay me an agreed-upon salary. Suppose, further, that after ten years of working for Amalgamated, I decide to go to work for another firm. If Amalgamated wants me to stay, and cannot otherwise persuade me to do so, would it be “illegal” for me to work elsewhere? Would the company have a legal right to compel me to continue working for it? Such a conclusion is implicit in the statists’ rejection of the right to secede.
    Sound analogy.

    When questions of secession are approached not in terms of consistency with some abstract, philosophic principle, but as a matter of realpolitik, it becomes evident who the real parties in interest are. It is not the system, the tool that advances the claim of its primacy, but those who have taken control of the instrument – or who were responsible for its creation in the first place – in order to use it to control others to advance their private purposes. The “cui bono” principle applies in this setting as much as it does elsewhere in human behavior: “who benefits,” not only from the creation of systems by which we organize ourselves, but in interpreting the words we employ in defining the scope of what such systems may do.
    I am favorably impressed. This man knows the correct questions to ask.

    When we attach ourselves so strongly to an abstraction that our minds have created, that we identify our very being with it; it becomes difficult for us to examine how such an attachment might contribute to the problems ensuing from our actions. To what extent, in other words, does our thinking contribute to the difficulties we experience in our institutionalized world?
    Brilliant. This is precisely what I have been writing about for years, e.g. The "State" This is the worse case scenario of confusing the map with the territory. This is literally and clinically assertable as cognitive disorder at the very least and more likely actual cognitive disease. It is psychosis in the most clinically literal sense.

    Whether we are considering questions in the realm of religion, science, law, or other subjects, we encounter a truth that few people are willing to consider: no system of thought can be self-validating. As Gregory Bateson emphasized, intellectual respect for any belief system cannot depend upon internal assertions, but must be analyzed from outside the system; to be tested by a metasystem (which, in turn, must be validated by yet another metasystem, ad infinitum).
    As stated, the bold text is demonstrably false. He may mean that it cannot be self-validating in an absolute fashion, and there he would be correct, but unless I am misconstruing his use of "self-validating", I would have to deem his assertion flawed. If there is no such thing as a self-validating system of thought, which is another term for some set of presumably fundamental conceptual constructs, then the world would be naught but chaos and I assert that it would be so to the extent that life itself would not be able to be sustained. The self-organizing nature of life itself would appear to contradict the author's claim. The quoted assertion of Bateson fails under close scrutiny because the so-called "metasystem" is itself a system that must in turn be validated by yet another such metasystem. The requirement of such a metasystem sets up an infinite regression of metasystems. It is a conceptual Ponzi scheme where irreducible bedrock postulates are never reached. This represents the architecture of FAIL. The prenthetical states precisely this. CRASH.

    There is, however, a way around this such that a self-validating conceptual framework may be constructed. One example is in fact the Canon of Individual Sovereignty which starts with an arbitrary premise that itself is plainly and resoundingly self-evident from the human perspective: All Men hold equal claims to Life. This postulate may not resound well with the Blignorbs from planet Grooblehink. They may be creatures of a fabric to far removed and foreign to that of the human creature that something utterly different may make sense to them in terms of the most irreducible truths by which they choose to live. That does not invalidate the human postulate for humans. It is sufficient that within the human context nobody is able to dislodge the fundamental logic of such a postulate with any credibility and that is the case with the Canon. The Cardinal Postulate is, in fact, unbreakable in terms of its truth value for reasons I will not go into here because of space requirements. Suffice to say that the Cardinal Postulate brings with it a truth of such force that it is a vanishing possibility that anyone would ever be able to break it. From that premise the body of eminently self-validating conceptual contructs arise. It is contained with a context, the human context, but that is all that should matter, at least until the Blignorbs or one of our other neighbors lands their ships on the South Lawn.

    Neither religion, nor science, nor any philosophic beliefs, nor legal maxims, can self-justify itself. One finds an illustration of this idea in the old story of the man who is explaining to his son the structure of the universe, whose vastness, he tells him, rests on the back of a turtle. “But upon what does this turtle rest?,” the boy asks. “Upon another turtle,” the father responds. “But, again, what supports this turtle?,” the bewildered lad inquires. “Look,” said he father, “it’s turtles all the way down!”
    Demonstrably untrue. That most or even all cannot TODAY is only evidence of rotten construction and not of the asserted impossibility. Big miss here. Turtle analogy is way off the mark here. I see exactly what he is attempting to do, but he is failing at is.

    This endless regression is present in every system of thought,
    No, it is most definitely not. It is only the case when one removes all context from the propositions in the attempt to render them absolute. When context is preserved, a relative form of the absolute is established and it is against this bedrock that all measurements are made.

    including the politico-legal system under question here. One of the first questions I ask my first-year students is this: “does the U.S. Constitution have any validity? And if so, why? Upon what basis does the government presume to rule your life?” This is one of those questions that few of us are ever encouraged to ask, leaving most of us to accept the political control of our lives with the same resignation we would the forces of gravity. Most of my students appear dumbfounded that such a question is even asked, particularly in a law school where the legitimacy of the Constitution is taken as a given. While the preamble presumes to speak for “We the People,” and Article V provides for the calling of a “Convention for proposing Amendments,” at no point is mention made of the right of people to secede, to withdraw from the system thus created.
    He returns to brilliance here - on the money. His failing, thus far, appears to be along a single and narrow line of consideration.

    By what metasystem might the question of the justifiability of the Constitution – and, with it, the entire political structure of the United States – be analyzed? If it cannot be validated by its own self-serving language, to what standard might we turn? One possibility is the Declaration of Independence, a document that created no political institution, but provided the criteria by which any such bodies might be judged. Philosophic or religious texts might also be useful, but given connections presumed to exist between these two instruments, I will use the Declaration for purposes of comparison.
    Not a metasystem as he uses here, but rather "standard". The standard is the equality of claim to life shared by all men. It is a standard whose simple elegance resonates intuitively with the vast majority of people. Even the candy-ass but nonetheless dangerous progressives appear to accept it. They're just too stupid to derive from it that which is so painfully obvious to intelligent people. They like the premise, but reject that which it so forcefully and directly implies. In other words, they are bat$#@! crazy, fearful, and dishonest.

    The Declaration – heavily influenced by the thinking of such persons as John Locke – rationalizes the relations between individuals and political systems on a contract theory. Individuals being free, by nature, to protect their lives and property – but not to aggress or steal from others – may join together to form agencies to provide such protection – but with the same limitations vis-à-vis their neighbors. Should the political system, thus produced, exceed its permitted boundaries, it is the right of the people to “alter or abolish” it, and to create a new system to promote such legitimate ends. The Declaration clearly expresses the rights to “abolish” or to secede from a government that violates the individual rights that transcend the powers of the state.
    Problem here, again, is the reference to "the people", which refers to nothing but a collection of individuals, each demonstrably free to come and go as per his stated specification and never bound by conrete to his fellows, save in the single prohibition of bringing unjust aggressions upon them.

    One can read through the Constitution for words that provide such precision in thought, but will not find it. In the 1857 words of Lord Macaulay, “Your Constitution is all sail and no anchor,” one finds the essence of state power in America. One provision in the Constitution that contains faint echoes of the sentiments of the Declaration is the Ninth Amendment, which reads: “The enumeration in the Constitution, of certain rights, shall not be construed to deny or disparage others retained by the people.” The logical implications of such words would lead thoughtful minds to acknowledge what the passage portends: the rights of human beings are of such infinite dimensions as to not be capable of verbalization. The Ninth Amendment was intended as a reminder of this fact.
    Fabulous, especially the sail-anchor quote. It is so very true. The spirit of the Constitution is to be commended, but the practicalities are terrible. In the practical aspect, it is a completely horrid document of endlessly poor contrivance. The Tenth Amendment is utter $#@! and should never have been included. The Ninth subsumes and supercedes it in valence and propriety.

    If the spirit of the Declaration was thus to be incorporated into the Constitution by this Amendment, one would expect hundreds or even thousands of cases to have arisen under it, and to have affirmed an expansive defense of the individual when confronted by the state. Such has not been the case. Only a handful of cases has arisen under the Ninth Amendment. This has contributed to the twisting of the thinking that places individual liberty above all interests of the state; thus creating a default-mode mindset that whatever “rights” people enjoy come from, and are “given” by, the Constitution. As a result of such intellectual corruption, it is commonplace for people to conclude that, if a purported “right” cannot be found in the specific language (aka as “strict construction”) of the Constitution, it does not exist!
    Unvarnished and unbreakable truth. The Tenth gets the attention because it glorifies that non-entity, "the state".

    It is on the basis of such thinking that politicians, judges, and other statists assert that “secession” is “illegal.” If the Constitution does not specifically provide for this remedy, it does not exist; it is unlawful to pursue it. That such a proposition negates not only the Declaration of Independence, but the “social contract” theory upon which the state depends for bamboozling the public, is conveniently ignored by the statists. Many even go so far as to argue that the Civil War proved the illegality of secession, a conclusion that disregards the American colonials seceding from their then-present British government in a Revolutionary War aided by the ideas and spirit in the Declaration of Independence.
    Nice.

    “Secession” is not a legal question, any more than it is a “scientific,” or “technological,” or “medical,” or even a “mathematics” issue. It is, rather, a proposition that cannot be intelligently explored, or acted upon, within the confines of the system from which secessionists seek to withdraw. It is, in other words, a philosophical question; one that requires recourse to deeply-held principled beliefs. Just as those nineteenth century libertarians who sought to abolish slavery had to rest their arguments on metasystems of thought that transcended constitutional, statutory, and other formal legal standards; the secession question cannot be answered by the political authorities who control, for their benefit, the coercive machinery that continues to grind down, loot, and destroy those who seek to liberate themselves from its inhumane practices.
    Agreed - thus illustrating they way(s) in which the Constitution is a failed construct.

    From what extra-legal thinking can thoughtful minds find the inspiration and questioning with which to move outside the rigidly maintained boundaries of legalism? When we recall that the post-World War II Nuremberg defendants sought to excuse their murderous conduct with the plea that the acts they performed were not only allowed, but mandated by German law, we ought to be skeptical of allowing any system humans have created to be the judges of its own validity.

    Whether mankind is to survive, or bring about its own extinction, will depend largely on the premises that underlie our social organizations. Will they exist as voluntary, cooperative systems through which individuals can mutually achieve their respective interests; or will they continue to function as herd-oriented collectives that allow the few to benefit at the expense of the many? The answers to such questions are to be found only within our individual thinking. Secession does not begin at the ballot box, or in courtrooms, or in signing petitions, but in the same realm where you lost your independence: within your mind, and your willingness to identify with conflict-ridden abstractions.
    Other than one or two fundamental errors in his reasoning, I would call this a brilliant piece.

    That said, I will also point out that in the last paragraph he fails to take into account the effects of technology. What he asserts about "social organizations" holds well enough where technology keeps individuals on a more or less parity-level with each other. But the notion of least common denominator comes into serious play where human relations are concerned - entropy itself. Those willing to stoop lower will often hold some material advantage over those who might retain to principle.

    If one gang develops hydrogen weaponry, the rest clamor to follow suit. Why? Not necessarily because they are blood thirsty lunatics champing at the bit to lay the big one on somebody, but more likely because they rightly distrust their neighbors when parity is disturbed in such ways. The logic of this is rather compelling at a gut level. one "society" develops the bomb while the other refrains. The first makes more and more, then decides to demand of the other all their natural resources, or become a satellite or whatever. Others say "go away" and are shortly thereafter bombed out of existence. This is what nations fear and rightly so because the track record of human history strongly suggests that this is precisely what will happen if parity is not maintained. Therefore, when Blovatia develops a new weapons obsoleting those of every other nation, those nations scramble to reestablish the balance. There goes a $#@!-ton of $$MOOLA.... and for what? To keep from being destroyed by another mob of $#@!-crazy humans whose advance beyond your own capabilities is well likely to lead them to some rather funny notions about things.

    Technology has changed EVERYTHING in terms of the political landscape and it has completely taken a giant $#@! on the human race - or rather, has provided the basis by which we have done so upon each other. Tech-enabled proclivity is at least as often a bad thing as good and as the tech balance between the haves and have-nots shifts away from the latter, the quality of life becomes ever lousier. The race, through its brilliant tech achievements, has painted itself into an untenable corner which I believe is going to end us up in very dire straits - far worse than we now occupy.

    Anyhow, overall I would rate this as a superb work.
    freedomisobvious.blogspot.com

    There is only one correct way: freedom. All other solutions are non-solutions.

    It appears that artificial intelligence is at least slightly superior to natural stupidity.

    Our words make us the ghosts that we are.

    Convincing the world he didn't exist was the Devil's second greatest trick; the first was convincing us that God didn't exist.

  6. #5
    Quote Originally Posted by osan View Post
    Anyhow, overall I would rate this as a superb work.
    Butler Shaffer [send him e-mail] teaches at the Southwestern University School of Law.
    Why not send Butler a copy of your review and critique of his article. He just may send a grade back to you.

  7. #6
    Anyone who advocates for secession needs to be rounded up and deported.

  8. #7
    Quote Originally Posted by 56ktarget View Post
    Anyone who advocates for secession needs to be rounded up and deported.
    Anyone who advocates rounding up and deporting secession advocates needs to be rounded up and deported.

  9. #8
    Quote Originally Posted by 56ktarget View Post
    Anyone who advocates for secession needs to be rounded up and deported.
    So much for progs' belief in the right to self-determination, eh?

    It's inevitable. This country is too big. Small is beautiful (another principle alleged "liberals" tossed aside in their insatiable lust for power and control).
    Last edited by Lucille; 04-04-2014 at 11:16 AM.
    Based on the idea of natural rights, government secures those rights to the individual by strictly negative intervention, making justice costless and easy of access; and beyond that it does not go. The State, on the other hand, both in its genesis and by its primary intention, is purely anti-social. It is not based on the idea of natural rights, but on the idea that the individual has no rights except those that the State may provisionally grant him. It has always made justice costly and difficult of access, and has invariably held itself above justice and common morality whenever it could advantage itself by so doing.
    --Albert J. Nock



  10. Remove this section of ads by registering.


Similar Threads

  1. Secession and the Law
    By Ronin Truth in forum Political Philosophy & Government Policy
    Replies: 0
    Last Post: 06-30-2014, 10:10 AM
  2. Secession
    By rp08orbust in forum U.S. Political News
    Replies: 8
    Last Post: 07-05-2009, 07:16 PM
  3. On Secession...
    By tonesforjonesbones in forum U.S. Constitution
    Replies: 3
    Last Post: 04-23-2009, 04:13 PM
  4. Secession
    By Acala in forum World News & Affairs
    Replies: 5
    Last Post: 08-28-2008, 07:13 PM

Posting Permissions

  • You may not post new threads
  • You may not post replies
  • You may not post attachments
  • You may not edit your posts
  •